Monday, October 24, 2005

A Common Law of Copy

The 1976 Act was the first of our copyright statutes to provide a definition of "copy" and of "fixed." Why did the 1976 Act break new ground in this respect? Although the 1909
Act didn't expressly require fixation, since generally it was limited to published works, the requirement was impliedly obvious. In a 1961 report to Congress on the revision of that Act, Register of Copyrights Abraham Kaminstein wrote it was "well established" that for a work to be a "writing," it had to be "fixed in some tangible form from which the work can be reproduced," 1961 Report at 9. (This belief, by the way, is why the bootleg statute in 1994 was enacted under the Commerce Clause).

In the 1976 Act, the concept of "copy" is intimately intertwined with that of fixation, since the definition of copy reads:

"Copies” are material objects, other than phonorecords, in which a work is fixed by any method now known or later developed, and from which the work can be perceived, reproduced, or otherwise communicated, either directly or with the aid of a machine or device. The term “copies” includes the material object, other than a phonorecord, in which the work is first fixed.

The definition of "fixed" in turn references "copy":

A work is “fixed" in a tangible medium of expression when its embodiment in a copy or phonorecord, by or under the authority of the author, is sufficiently permanent or stable to permit it to be perceived, reproduced, or otherwise communicated for a period of more than transitory duration. A work consisting of sounds, images, or both, that are being transmitted, is “fixed” for purposes of this title if a fixation of the work is being made simultaneously with its transmission.

So why the definitions? The definition of copy came first, in 1965, in order to draw a distinction (made eventually in Section 202) between the material object and the intangible property. The definition of "fixed" came in 1966, in conjunction with the addition of audiovisual works as a separate category of subject matter in Section 102, and was intended to exclude from protection purely evanescent images. "Fixed," therefore, had to do with protectibility, and "copy" had to do with the difference between object and subject.

Both terms, have, however, had their greatest application for a very different and one would have expected, controversial purpose, infringement. The bellweather of the storm is the 9th Circuit's opinion in MAI Systems Corp. v. Peak Computer, Inc., 991 F.2d 511 (9th Cir. 1993). That opinion held that the internal creation of a "copy" of software in RAM for diagnostic purposes was an infringing (as outside of a license) copy. The relevant discussion is surprisingly brief:

"Peak argues that this loading of copyrighted software does not constitute a copyright violation because the "copy" created in RAM is not 'fixed.' However, by showing that Peak loads the software into the RAM and is then able to view the system error log and diagnose the problem with the computer. MAI has adequately shown that the representation created in the RAM is 'sufficiently permanent or stable to permit it to be perceived, reproduced, or otherwise communicated for a period of more than transitory duration.'"

This approach confuses "fixed" and "copy" for protectibility purposes with "copy" in the infringement sense. The concept of "copy" in the infringement sense predates the definition of "copy" in the 1976 Act by over two hundred years, and as noted last week, has had, historically, a limited application; that is, many substantial reproductions (like fair abridgments and translations) were not deemed a "copy" at the infringement stage, even though the unauthorized work was quite fixed.

The 9th Circuit falsely conflated two very different concepts. The first concept is the degree to which an original work is a will-o'-wisp. The second concept is whether a concededly protected work has, to a material degree, been reproduced. The 9th Circuit and its progeny have assumed that because a temporary copy usually is of the entirety of the work, there is no question about it being a "copy" in the infringement senses. I think that is not necessarily true. Why, for example, shouldn't the infringement concept of "copy" take into account, as it historically did before 1976, a host of policy considerations such as the purpose of the copying and the benefit to the public from the use? It is not, fair use, by the way, that has a monopoly on such policy considerations; another example is the idea-expression dichotomy, a common law foundation of copyright.

The contours of "copy" in the infringement sense is a third example. Importantly, Congress declined to include a definition of infringement, that is "copy" in this sense, preferring to leave the matter up to the courts to handle in a common law manner. How bizarre, then, that a definition of "copy" included for a different purpose has not only come to serve as a definition Congress declined to provide, but, like Section 107, has served to prevent courts from continuing as common law adjudicators when new technological challenges are presented.

The critical error in the 9th Circuit's analysis, then, is that "copy" for infringement purposes is a common law concept; it is not co-extensive with (and maybe does not overlap at all) with the statutory definition, which is concerned with something else entirely. There is another parallel with fair use. The statutory recognition of fair use has had a devastating impact, misleading some courts into thinking Section 107 "codifies" fair use and leading to a 4-step by-the-numbers analysis. Instead, courts should view fair use for what it is, a common law concept; while courts must glance at the statutory factors, they are not bound by them and can find them helpful, determinative, or unhelpful, and they can create and apply their own considerations.

If defendant's "fixation" is evanescent, as in buffering or caching why, for infringement purposes, should it be deemed a "copy"? Such copying is not being done for its own value, but rather to facilitate a non-infringing use, such as a licensed public performance. Might not the same be true for intermediate copying and other copying technologically necessary for non-infringing activity (like limited searching of books)?

Thinking of "copy" all the lines suggested here would be more consistent with the historical meaning of the term, the purposes of copyright, and the purposes for the definitions of "fixed" and "copies." It is the 9th Circuit's approach that is revolutionary.

2 comments:

Anonymous said...

Thank you for pointing out correctly I think that fixation as an investitive component of copyright requires a "copy" different in kind and in sense than the form of "copy" potentially necessary for infringement. The 6th Circuit in Bridgeport Music v. Dimension Films could have used your instruction. But I disagree with where you are headed at the end of your post:
If defendant's "fixation" is evanscent, as in buffering or caching why, for infringement purposes, should it be deemed a "copy"? Such copying is not being done for its own value, but rather to facilitate a non-infringing use, such as a licensed public performance. Might not the same be true for intermediate copying and other copying technologically necessary for non-infringing activity (like limited searching of books)?
I prefer to think of the investitive "copy" as the "original fixed work" and subsequent duplicates as "copies." There is no more fundamental aspect to copyright than the exclusive grant to the author of the right to make and license copies of the original work. Perhaps in origin this fundamental right spoke to printed copies in physical form, just as writings were limited, by and large, to tracings on paper. But technology long ago evolved past printing and the stylus and copyright has adapted. Long debates and subsequent rules on the ephemeral copies by broadcasters, for example, suggest that the meaning of an infringing copy is much more particular, as a matter of statutory definition, than you suggest. And consider a logical extension pre-digital analogy to what you have suggested - - an orchestral work rendered as a lawful public performance absolving the company performing it from paying for rental sheets because looking at the sheet music is just an evanescent intermediate step necessary to a lawful end.

William Patry said...

Anonymous said:

"But technology long ago evolved past printing and the stylus and copyright has adapted. Long debates and subsequent rules on the ephemeral copies by broadcasters, for example, suggest that the meaning of an infringing copy is much more particular, as a matter of statutory definition, than you suggest. And consider a logical extension pre-digital analogy to what you have suggested - - an orchestral work rendered as a lawful public performance absolving the company performing it from paying for rental sheets because looking at the sheet music is just an evanescent intermediate step necessary to a lawful end."

I certainly accept that copyright has long evolved past the printing press and vinyl records, but I am not so confident that it has adjusted very well either at the protection side or the infringement side. The Supreme Court's pre-1976 Act trilogy of cable TV opinions illustrate that. the Court's splitting 4 to 4 in Williams and Wilkins on a technologically simple issue like photocopying. The Court's different 5-4 votes in Sony, its botching of fair use in that opinion (principally the creation of presumptions), the Court's 4 to 4 split in Lotus v. Borland, and what I have viewed as the Court's punting in Grokster. To me, there is little reason to express confidence that things have or will go well. Industries have coped, of course, and it is a testament to them that they have overcome such hurdles.

The focus on my posting is with a narrow area where I think courts have done a singularly poor job of adjusting and that is in updating what should constitute infringement when a copy is made as a means to a different, non-infringing end. I think boradcasters shouldn't have liability for ephemeral copies if the boradcast is licensed, and by emphemeral I mean a copy made for broadcast that same day, and not librarying. The orchestra example given isn't to me quite on all fours because no copy was made. A slightly different version of your argument I think is troubling. Let's say I have perfect recollection: I look at a score in a music store and then go out an engage in a licensed public performance. Should I have to pay for looking at the score?

The approach I outlined is preliminary, more of offering a different way to think about things, but to me, treating ephemeral copies as if they are permanent hard copies the way the law currently does is the opposite of adapting; it is precisely treating them as if we were in 1710 or 1790.